Efficiency
Design legal system that obtains efficient outcomes
If transaction costs are low, with well-defined and tradeable property rights, parties can bargain voluntarily to reach the efficient outcome.
So the initial allocation of rights doesn't matter for efficiency
But if transaction costs are high, we may not get the efficient outcome
Led us to two normative guidelines for designing an efficient legal system:
Tradeoff between injunctive relief and damages
Law of property works well for spot transactions
Law of contracts allow for more complicated non-simultaneous trade
So far, we have only examined voluntary exchange and mutual consent
Up next: “involuntary exchange”
Property law: situations where transaction costs are low enough to get agreement ahead of time (some exceptions of course!)
Contract law: situations where transaction costs are low enough for us to agree to a contract, but high enough that we might not want to renegotiate the contract later (when something unexpected happens)
Tort law: situations where transaction costs are too high to agree on anything in advance
Example: I am distracted and hit you with my car while you are bicycling to class
Put aside questions of justice and retribution...and simply consider incentives
Distracted driving (and hitting people) clearly imposes a serious negative externality on others
Without any laws, we expect more than the efficient amount of distracted driving
Society needs to design law to discourage this behavior
Harder with tort law, because I did not intend to hit you (and we had no prior agreement)
I made a choice ahead of time (to be distracted) that increased the likelihood of an accident
Harder with tort law, because I did not intend to hit you (and we had no prior agreement)
I made a choice ahead of time (to be distracted) that increased the likelihood of an accident
Harder with tort law, because I did not intend to hit you (and we had no prior agreement)
I made a choice ahead of time (to be distracted) that increased the likelihood of an accident
So how do we create an incentive to avoid this type of outcome?
Can imagine several ways
Punish the choice (criminal law, regulations): make it illegal to drive distracted (even if you don't hit anyone)
Punish the outcome (“Strict liability”): if you hit someone, regardless of the choice you made, (distracted or not), you are liable
Punish the choice (criminal law, regulations): make it illegal to drive distracted (even if you don't hit anyone)
Punish the outcome (“Strict liability”): if you hit someone, regardless of the choice you made, (distracted or not), you are liable
Punish the combination of choice & outcome (““Negligence”): if you hit someone, and you made a bad choice increasing the probability of an accident, you are liable
Tort: noun. (French): injury
Contract law: where someone harms you by breaking a promise they made
Tort law: where someone harms you without having made any promises
“If someone shoots you, call a cop. If someone hits your car, call a lawyer.”
As usual, we will focus on attaining efficient outcomes
I hit you with my car, causing $1,000 worth of damage to you (no damage to me)
Suppose the law holds me liable for:
Nothing | $1,000 | $50,000 | |
---|---|---|---|
You | -1,000 | 0 | 49,000 |
Me | 0 | -1,000 | -50,000 |
Joint | -1,000 | -1,000 | -1,000 |
Whatever happens after the accident has no apparent effect on efficiency
...this can't be the way to think about efficiency
Everything that happens after the accident merely affects distribution, not efficiency
Damage is already done, lawsuit = how to clean up the mess:
These were made based on expectations about what will happen
These decisions affect the outcomes and how much value is created and destroyed by society
More importantly, how do laws and court decisions affect future behavior on the margin?
Economists are more forward-looking about law
How do we structure tort law to get people to behave in a way that results in efficient outcomes?
For deliberate harms: make punishments severe (criminal law)
For accidental harms, much trickier
How do we structure tort law to get people to behave in a way that results in efficient outcomes?
Unlike property law, no injunctive relief possible
Unlike contract law, no agreement in advance
Cooter and Ulen: essence of tort law is
“the attempt to make injurers internalize the externalities they cause, in situations where transaction costs are too high to do this through property or contract rights”
Plaintiff: person who brings the lawsuit
Defendant: person who is being sued
In a tort case, Defendant caused some harm to Plaintiff, who is asking for damages
Like contract law, a well-known legal theory of tort liability developed 100 years ago
A valid tort case (where Plaintiff can collect damages from Defendant) has three elements:
For a tort to exist, the Plaintiff needs to have suffered some harm
“Without harm, there is no tort”
Examples:
Consider some preference relationship between money and health
Accident has caused injured party (Plaintiff) to suffer harm
Consider some preference relationship between money and health
Accident has caused injured party (Plaintiff) to suffer harm
Perfect compensation would restore Plaintiff to original level of well-being
Many of the harms are tangible:
But there can also be intangible harms:
Should we compensate for intangible harms?
Pros: the closer liability is to the full harm done, the better the incentive to avoid these harms (internalize the full externality)
Cons: hard to measure, subjective value, high variance in award sizes, incentive to rent-seek?
To be liable for a tort, the Plaintiff must show that the Defendant caused them harm
Cause-in-fact test
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“I stop my friend in the street to chat. He continues on down the street. As he passes by an office building, a safe falls out the window and crushes him. Have I caused his death? Should I be liable?
One sense of “I caused his death” is “had I not acted as I did, he would not have died”—the “but for” definition of causality. In that sense I killed my friend—if I had not delayed him, he would not have been under the safe when it fell. Yet it would seem odd to blame me and odder still to hold me liable. Why?” (p.191)
Palsgraf v. Long Island Rairoad Co., 248 N.Y. 339 (1928)
Railroad attendant’s actions caused, but were not the proximate cause to Ms. Palgraf's injuries
Court ruled attendant’s actions were too remote to be considered a proximate cause
“Plaintiff [Mrs. Palsgraf] was standing on a platform of defendant’s railroad after buying a ticket to go to Rockaway Beach. A train stopped at the station, bound for another place. Two men ran forward to catch it. One of the men reached the platform of the car without mishap, though the train was already moving. The other man, carrying a pack- age, jumped aboard the car, but seemed unsteady as if about to fall. A guard on the car, who had held the door open, reached forward to help him in, and another guard on the platform pushed him from behind. In this act, the package was dislodged, and fell upon the rails. It was a package of small size, about fifteen inches long, and was covered by a newspaper. In fact it contained fireworks, but there was nothing in its appearance to give notice of its contents. The fireworks when they fell exploded. The shock of the ex- plosion threw down some scales at the other end of the platform many feet away. The scales struck the plaintiff, causing injuries for which she sues.”
Source: Court Opinion
Benjamin N. Cardozo
1870—1938
Associate Justice of U.S. Supreme Court
“Negligence, like risk, is thus a term of relation. Negligence in the abstract, apart from things related, is surely not a tort, if indeed it is understandable at all...Negligence is not a tort unless it results in the commission of a wrong, and the commission of a wrong imports the violation of a right, in this case, we are told, the right to be protected against interference with one's bodily security.”
“[T]he conduct of the defendant's guard, if a wrong in its relation to the holder of the package, was not a wrong in its relation to the plaintiff, standing far away. Relative to her it was not negligence at all...proof of negligence in the air, so to speak, will not do...a different conclusion will involve us, and swiftly too, in a maze of contradictions.”
Source: Court Opinion
Proximate cause: defendant's actions must not be too distant from the event that caused the actual harm to Plaintiff
But no precise legal definition of how close “proximate” is
Breach of duty is sometimes, but not always necessary for a tort to exist
Depends on the liability rule in place!
Consider two different tort liability rules: strict liability and negligence
Strict Liability | Negligence |
---|---|
Strict Liability | Negligence |
---|---|
1. Harm | |
2. Causation | |
Strict Liability | Negligence |
---|---|
1. Harm | 1. Harm |
2. Causation | 2. Causation |
3. Breach of duty (fault) |
So under a negligence rule:
If I breach by due of due care and injure you, I am liable
If I exercise the appropriate level of care but still injure you, I am not liable
How is the standard of care determined?
In some settings, governments impose safety regulations used as the standard for negligence
Some standards are left vauge
Strict liability rule: Plaintiff must prove harm and causation
Negligence rule: Plaintiff must prove harm, causationn, and negligence
Historical development
Keyboard shortcuts
↑, ←, Pg Up, k | Go to previous slide |
↓, →, Pg Dn, Space, j | Go to next slide |
Home | Go to first slide |
End | Go to last slide |
Number + Return | Go to specific slide |
b / m / f | Toggle blackout / mirrored / fullscreen mode |
c | Clone slideshow |
p | Toggle presenter mode |
t | Restart the presentation timer |
?, h | Toggle this help |
Esc | Back to slideshow |