Recalling in property law:
Similarly with contract law:
Situations where promise will not be enforced and no compensation is due
Two categories of conditions:
Formation defenses
Performance excuses
Main goal of contract is facilitating gains from trade for efficiency
Economic theory teaches us that competitive markets maximize gains from trade (and efficiency) when:
Violations of these conditions often imply a market failure
Contract that violates the law is unenforceable
Less obvious: contracts that derogate public policy are also unenforceable
Recall inalienability rules; enforcing these contracts creates negative externalities
Party that reasonably knew performance was illegal should be liable
Courts will not enforce contracts with people with mental incapacity (lack of rationality) — incapable of understanding the implications of a contract
Doctrine of incompetence: one party “not competent to enter into the agreement”
“The kid bid about $113,000 on the aircraft at a fixed price...The kid’s dad notified the seller that his son had hit the buy now button and lacked the money in his piggy bank to cover the jet.”
What about if you signed a contract while drunk?
Need to be really really really drunk to get out a contract
“Intoxicated to the extent of being unable to comprehend the nature and consequences of the instrument he executed.”
Lucy v. Zehmer Virginia Sup Ct 1954
Zehmer owned a farm (“the Ferguson farm”), Lucy had been trying to buy it for some time
While out drinking, Lucy “already high as a Georgia pine” offers $50,000
“We hereby agree to sell W.O. Lucy the Ferguson Farm complete for $50,000.00, title satisfactory to buyer.”
A day later, Lucy raises money to carry out the contract
Zehmer later claims he was drunk and joking: “a bunch of two doggoned drunks bluffing to see who could talk the biggest and say the most”
Lucy sues for specific performance: court issuing an order for the contract to be performed as specified (i.e. Zehmer sell to Lucy for $50,000)
Lucy v. Zehmer 196 Va. 493; 84 S.E.2d 516 (1954)
Court: Zehmer not so drunk as to be “unable to comprehend the nature and consequences” of what he was doing
Joke or not, Zehmer behaved exactly as if he actually wanted to sell, wrote what looked like a proper (if unorthodox) contract
Court held the contract was valid and Zehmer owed specific performance
Might think Zehmer, being drunk, lacked necessary intent to enter into a contract
Makes more sense to not easily invalidate a contract just for drunkenness/joking
If you are visibly drunk and other party clearly knows, court might be more willing to invalidate (on some other grounds coming soon)
Moral of the story: don’t get drunk with people who might ask you to sign a contract!
“Two college fraternity buddies shown guzzling alcohol and making racist remarks in the “Borat” movie have lost their bid for a court order to cut the scene they claim has tarnished their reputations...The students sued the movie’s distributor and producers last month, saying filmmakers had duped them into appearing in “Borat” by getting them drunk and falsely promising the film would never be shown in the United States.”
“The scene at issue in the lawsuit depicts Borat getting drunk with three frat boys in a motor home while they watch a sex tape and make racist remarks about slavery and minorities in the United States.”
Source: Reuters (Jan 20, 2007)
See also this great legal analysis of this case, has to do with the validity of “merger clauses” in contracts
Court will not enforce contracts made under dire constraints, e.g.:
Necessity
Court will not enforce contracts made under dire constraints, e.g.:
Duress
“A man who held a Kansas couple hostage in their home while fleeing from authorities is suing them, claiming they broke an oral contract made when he promised them money in exchange for hiding him from police. The couple has asked a judge to dismiss the suit...Jesse Dimmick of suburban Denver is serving an 11-year sentence after bursting into Jared and Lindsay Rowley's Topeka-area home in September 2009...Dimmick filed a breach of contract suit in Shawnee County District Court.”
“‘I, the defendant, asked the Rowleys to hide me because I feared for my life. I offered the Rowleys an unspecified amount of money which they agreed upon, therefore forging a legally binding oral contract,’ Dimmick said in his hand-written court documents. He wants $235,000, in part to pay for the hospital bills that resulted from him being shot by police when they arrested him.”
Source: Yahoo Finance (Nov 29, 2011)
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“A mugger catches you alone in a dark alley and offers you a choice: Give him a hundred dollars or he kills you. You reply that your life is well worth the price, but unfortunately you are not carrying that much cash. He offers to take a check. When you get home, should you be free to stop payment? Should a contract made under duress be enforceable?” (p.152)
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“The argument in favor of enforceability is that if the contract is not enforceable, the mugger will refuse your check—or accept it and then make sure you can’t stop payment by killing you and cashing the check before news of your death reaches the bank. Seen from that perspective, it looks as though even a contract made under duress produces benefits for both parties and so should be enforceable. You prefer paying a hundred dollars to being killed, he prefers receiving a hundred dollars to killing you. Where’s the problem?
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“The problem is that making the contract enforceable makes offering people the choice between their money and their life a much more profitable business—most of us have more in our checking accounts than in our wallets. The gain from enforceability is a better chance, if you are mugged, to buy yourself free. It must be balanced against the higher probability of being mugged. It seems likely that the current legal rule, holding contracts made under duress unenforceable, is the efficient one.”
Recall Efficiency requires enforcing a contract if both parties wanted it to be enforceable
So why not enforce it?
Tradeoff: refuse to enforce a Pareto-improving trade in order to avoid incentive for bad behavior
Tradeoff means not always optimal to rule out enforceability under duress!
Example: what about peace treaties between nations at war?
Most people agree peace treaties being enforceable is a good thing
Likely efficient for peace treaties to be enforceable but promises made a mugger to not be!
Courts won’t enforce contracts made under threat of harm
But many negotiations contain threats
More subtle in cases involving contract modification: changes to contract made between formation & performance
“Preexisting duty” rule: law only recognizes changes to contract supported by new consideration
What if events cause a party to agree to a modification that she later regrets? Coerced?
Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (117 F. 99, 9th Cir. 1902)
APA hired sailors to go fishing for salmon off coast of Alaska
Once at sea, sailors refused to work unless their wage was increased
Alaska Packers’ Association v Domenico (117 F. 99, 9th Cir. 1902)
Court voided the new contract on grounds that there was no additional consideration to support the promised wage increase
Want to avoid monopoly power and one-sided bargaining power
Goebel v. Linn (47 Mich. 489, 11 N.W. 284, 1882)
Brewery contracted with ice company to supply ice during the summer
Unusually warm winter caused ice shortage
Brewery later reneged on paying the higher price
Goebel v. Linn (47 Mich. 489, 11 N.W. 284, 1882)
Seems like straightforward application of preexisting duty rule (?)
Court enforced the modification in this case!
These cases show “economic duress” is really about preventing monopoly power
Alaska Packers case was pure opportunism, no genuine economic changes
Goebel case was a genuine economic change (supply curve shifted upward)
Recall: under bargain theory, courts will enforce any legitimate bargain, not inquire whether the terms are fair
Primarily rely on statutes to reduce monopoly power
But there is a growing body of precedent in common law banning contracts that are unconscionable
Logic: party would not have voluntarily accepted such terms, must have been either incompetent, under duress, or defrauded
Court shifts burden to defendant to prove that contract was fair when it was agreed to
Williams v. Walker-Thomas Furniture Co. (350 F.2d 445, D.C. Cir. 1965)
WT Co. extended credit to Williams to buy several pieces of furniture over 1957-1962
Court ruled the clause unconscionable, grossly unfair to low-income buyers (form of economic duress)
“[W]e hold that where the element of unconscionability is present at the time a contract is made, the contract should not be enforced....Unconscionability has generally been recognized to include an absence of meaningful choice on the part of one of the parties together with contract terms which are unreasonably favorable to the other party....In many cases the meaningfulness of the choice is negated by a gross inequality of bargaining power.”
Williams v. Walker-Thomas Furniture Co. (350 F.2d 445, D.C. Cir. 1965)
But is this efficient?
A tradeoff:
Of course consumers can be taken advantage of by complex contracts
Ideally, evidence of incompetence, duress, or fraud should be external to the contract itself
Unconscionability tends not to be invoked in usual circumstances of monopoly, but in “situational monopoly”
Recall Ploof v. Putnam (boat in storm) from property law
Next, a performance excuse, impossibility: circumstances change to make performance of the contract impossible
Should the promisor be excused from performing (without penalty)?
A perfect contract would specify who bears each risk, or industry custom might be clear, but occasionally court must fill in gap
Sometimes excused by physical impossibility
Examples:
Common legal doctrine to excuse due to a change that “destroyed a basic assumption on which the contract was made”
What would be efficient? Assign liability to the party who can bear the risk at the lowest cost
In many cases, parties can invest in precautions to minimize these risks of breach
Similar to our findings about gaps, risk from gap should be borne by party that can minimize risk cheapest
Spreading losses across many transactions
Moral hazard: who is in a better position to influence the outcome?
Adverse selection: who is more aware of the risk, even if they can’t do anything about it?
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“Suppose I am having a house built by a large firm that builds many houses each year. There is some risk that the house might burn down while it is being built. We could allocate that risk either to me, by specifying that I will have to pay for the additional construction costs in such a case, or to the builder. Since the builder is building many houses in different places, he can spread the risk; I cannot. From that standpoint at least, our contract should specify a fixed price, whether or not something goes wrong. If the contract does not specify who bears the risk, risk spreading provides an argument for assigning it to the builder” (p.161).
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“In the case of a firm that builds houses the two arguments go in the same direction. The builder is not only in a better position than I am to spread the risk, he is also in a better position than I am to keep the house from burning down while he is building it” (p.161).
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“I have agreed to deliver ten thousand customized widgets to you by January 10th. Early on the morning of January 1st a drunk driver smashes his car through the wall of my warehouse, crushing half the widgets. One result is that I will have to replace them, at a cost of a hundred thousand dollars. A second is that I will deliver them a month late, costing you another hundred thousand dollars in lost sales. The drunk driver is dead, and his estate bankrupt. Who pays for the losses?” (p.161).
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“I did not know that that particular drunk driver was going to crash through that particular wall. But I probably do know a good deal more than you do about the chance that something — accident, strike, or bad planning — will prevent me from delivering the widgets to you on schedule.
“If our contract makes me liable for the resulting loss, you don’t have to worry about that risk in deciding whom to buy your widgets from. You know what price I am charging, and you know that I am insuring you against the risk of nondelivery. If the contract specified that you had to bear the risk, you would need to know the reliability of alternative sellers as well as their price in order to decide which one is offering the best deal,” (p.162).
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“As this example suggests, moral hazard and adverse selection tend to cut in the same direction. As a general rule the party with control over some part of the production process is in a better position both to prevent losses and to predict them. It follows that an efficient contract will usually assign the loss associated with something going wrong to the party with control over that particular something,” (p.162).
That’s why Hadley v. Baxendale rule was so “surprising”
But court ruled Baxendale was not liable for Hadley’s lost profits, forcing Hadley to bear most of the delay risk/loss
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“A professional photographer spends six months taking photographs in the Himalayas for National Geographic, at a cost of a hundred thousand dollars. When he gets home, he gives his film to the local Walgreen’s — which loses it. Do they owe him a hundred thousand dollars?
“From the standpoint of risk spreading the answer would be ‘yes.’ Walgreen’s handles a large number of rolls of films each year, so it can easily pool the risk. From the standpoint of moral hazard, incentives to keep the loss from happening, the answer is ‘no,’” (p.161).
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“Walgreen’s has no way of knowing that there is anything special about these rolls of film. The only way they can prevent the loss is by increased precautions on all rolls. They have the choice of an inefficiently low level of care for ten rolls of film or an inefficiently high level for ten million. The photographer does know that these films are especially valuable and can avoid the problem by taking them to a specialist film lab and making sure the proprietor realizes what they are. The efficient rule from the standpoint of moral hazard is to make the photographer liable, because he is the one in the best position to prevent the loss. That, called the rule of Hadley v. Baxendale after an early case, is in fact the law.” ” (p.162).
What if the parties made a contract based on a mistake
Four major legal doctrines for invalidating a contract based on faulty information
Fraud: one party deliberately tricked the other
Economic rationale for not enforcing contracts with fraud is obvious
Also carries criminal sanctions — the State (as a third party) has an interest in deterring and punishing fraud
What if you trick someone by witholding information?
In civil law systems, a duty to disclose
In common law, less so
Obde v. Schlemeyer (Sup. Ct. WA 1960)
Seller knew building was infested with termites, did not tell buyer
Court imposed duty to disclose onto the contract, i.e. awarded damages to buyer
Fraud & failure to disclose are situations where one party is misinformed
What if both parties are misinformed?
Frustration of purpose: change in circumstances make performance of a promise pointless, court will often not enforce the contract
Coronation parade for King Edward VII, 1902
When a contingency makes performance pointless, assign liability to party who can bear risk at least cost
Similar to efficient rule above
Coronation parade for King Edward VII, 1902
Mutual mistake about facts: circumstances changed without either party realizing
Examples:
Owner at time of event (fire) usually the low-cost avoider of the risk, allocate risk to them by invalidating contract
“One neighbor offers to sell a used car to another for $1000. The buyer gives the money to the seller, and the seller gives the car keys to the buyer. To her great surprise, the buyer discovers that the keys fit the rusting Chevrolet in the back yard, not the shiny Cadillac in the driveway. The seller is equally surprised to learn that the buyer expected the Cadillac. The buyer asks the court to order the seller to turn over the Cadillac.”
“One neighbor offers to sell a used car to another for $1000. The buyer gives the money to the seller, and the seller gives the car keys to the buyer. To her great surprise, the buyer discovers that the keys fit the rusting Chevrolet in the back yard, not the shiny Cadillac in the driveway. The seller is equally surprised to learn that the buyer expected the Cadillac. The buyer asks the court to order the seller to turn over the Cadillac.”
Efficiency generally requires uniting knowledge and control
Contracts that unite knowledge & control are generally efficient, should be enforced
Contracts that separate knowledge from control may be inefficient, should more often be invalidated
Example: recall Hadley v. Baxendale (miller & shipper)
Hadley knew shipment was urgent (but didn’t tell Baxendale)
But Baxendale was the decisionmaker over how fast crankshaft would be shipped
Party that had the information ≠ party that makes the decision
What if one party does not have full information but the other does?
Example: a boy buys a baseball card from a shop, realizes it is worth a lot of money, resells it for large profit
Courts generally enforce (that is, they don’t invalidate) contracts where there is a unilateral mistake
Beliefs by parties about value of good is subjective and not determinable
Why is this efficient?
Contracts based on unilateral mistake generally unite knowledge & control
An enforcing them creates an incentive to gather information prior to agreement
Laidlaw v. Organ, 15 U.S. 178 (1817)
War of 1812, British blockaded New Orleans
Organ (buyer) learned the war was over
Next day, news broke that the war had ended, tobacco price went up
“It would be difficult to circumscribe the contrary doctrine within proper limits, where the means of intelligence are equally accessible to both parties. But at the same time, each party must take care not to say or do any thing tending to impose upon the other”
Adopts the rule of caveat emptor in American law
Doctrine gets a bit fuzzy from here, not a rock-solid rule
Laidlaw establishes that contracts based on unilateral mistake are generally valid
Organ didn’t invest time & resouces into seeking out this information for a productive purpose, happened upon it fortuitously
Contract merely accelerated the discovery of public information by one day, didn’t affect tobacco production
What about Obde v. Schlemeyer (termites case)?
Court upheld contract, but punished seller for hiding information
Productive information: information that can be used to produce more wealth
Redistributive information: information that can be used to redistribute wealth from an uninformed party to an informed party
Cooter & Ulen: contracts based on one party’s knowledge of:
Keyboard shortcuts
↑, ←, Pg Up, k | Go to previous slide |
↓, →, Pg Dn, Space, j | Go to next slide |
Home | Go to first slide |
End | Go to last slide |
Number + Return | Go to specific slide |
b / m / f | Toggle blackout / mirrored / fullscreen mode |
c | Clone slideshow |
p | Toggle presenter mode |
t | Restart the presentation timer |
?, h | Toggle this help |
Esc | Back to slideshow |