Predicting consequences of law
Predicting what law will be
Recommending what law should be
Positive economics: descriptive statements about the world
Normative economics: prescriptive statements about how the world ought to be
“Fiat justitia ruat caelum”
What is justice?
Utilitarian & deontological views of justice (among others)
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“The statement that we should choose just rules, while emotionally satisfying, does not convey much information. Economic value may capture only part of what we want out of a legal system, but at least economic theory tells us how to get it. And consequences are an important part of what we want. The doctrine fiat justicia, ruat coelum (let justice be done though the skies fall) is, in my experience, uniformly proclaimed by people who are confident that doing justice will not, in fact, bring down the sky,” (p.22).
David D. Friedman
(1945—)
“As we develop the economic analysis of law, we will observe a surprising correspondence between justice and efficiency. In many cases principles we think of as just correspond fairly to rules that we discover are efficient...This suggests a radical conjecture—that what we call principles of justice may actually be rules of thumb for producing an efficient outcome, rules we have somehow internalized. Whether that is a sufficient account of justice you will have to decide for yourself,” (p.22-23).
Richard A. Posner
1939—
Fmr. U.S. 7th Circuit Judge
Major figure in Law & Economics field
1981—2017 Judge of U.S Court of Appeals for the 7th Circuit
University of Chicago Law Professor
Considered for U.S. Supreme Court, but too pragmatic & libertarian-ish
The most cited legal scholar of the 20th (and 21st) Century
Absolutely prolific scholarly output
Richard A. Posner
1939—
Fmr. U.S. 7th Circuit Judge
Defends Kaldor-Hicks efficiency, or “wealth-maximization” approach to law
Notion of consent as “ex-ante compensation”
We often consent ex-ante to the possibility of many involuntary, uncompensated losses
Example: If you buy a lottery ticket and you don't win anything, you have consented to the loss (and deserve no compensation)
Posner, Richard A, 1980, “The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication,” Hofstra Law Review 8: 487
Richard A. Posner
1939—
Fmr. U.S. 7th Circuit Judge
Imagine before we all drive, everyone got together and negotiated a liability rule for traffic accidents
If one rule was clearly more efficient than another, we would all vote for that rule
The rule has our ex-ante consent (before any accident occurs)
Posner, Richard A, 1980, “The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication,” Hofstra Law Review 8: 487
Rule | Expected Payoff for Drivers | Expected Payoff for Pedestrians | Expected Payoff for Unknown in Advance |
---|---|---|---|
Strict Liability | -100 | 0 | -50 |
Negligence | -20 | -60 | -40 |
Consider two potential tenancy laws, one that is “tenant-friendly” and one that is “landlord-friendly”
But rents are determined competitively!
If the tenant-friendly law is less efficient, nobody would agree to it ex-ante (both sides harmed)
Richard A. Posner
1939—
Fmr. U.S. 7th Circuit Judge
If we choose the most efficient legal system, everyone is “compensated ex-ante”, should willingly accept the outcome they get
As members of society, our choosing efficient rules compensates us ex-ante, since these are the “lottery tickets” with the highest expected value
Posner, Richard A, 1980, “The Ethical and Political Basis of the Efficiency Norm in Common Law Adjudication,” Hofstra Law Review 8: 487
The “lottery ticket” analogy assumes risk neutrality
And equal marginal utility of money
Highlights some of the things that efficiency is not:
A famous trade-off between efficiency and equity
Robert C. Ellickson
“[W]hen people are situated in a close-knit group, they will tend to develop for the ordinary run of problems norms that are wealth-maximizing.”
“A norm is wealth-maximizing when it operates to minimize the members' objective sum of (1) transaction costs, and (2) deadweight losses arising from failures to exploit potential gains from trade,” (p.84).
Ellickson, Robert C, 1989, “A Hypothesis of Wealth-Maximizing Norms: Evidence from the Whaling Industry,” Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization 5(1): 83-97
Steven Landsburg
“I think economists are right to emphasize efficiency, and I think so for (at least) two reasons. First, emphasizing efficiency forces us to concentrate on the most important problems...
“In fact, whenever a policy is inefficient, there’s always an alternative policy that, in principle, is better for everyone. That’s what inefficiency means...
“So maybe we don’t want to pursue this alternative policy after all. But, says the economist, we ought at least to consider it...
“And — here’s the point — the bigger the deadweight loss, the greater the potential gains from an alternative policy. Therefore, the bigger the deadweight loss, the more it’s worth at least attempting to devise a good alternative policy. We calculate the deadweight loss as a rough but useful guide to how much effort we should put into this problem. (Calculating deadweight losses is the same thing as worrying about efficiency.)”
Landsburg, Steven, August 30, 2011, “Efficiency Experts”
Steven Landsburg
“Second, emphasizing efficiency forces us to be honest about our goals...efficiency analysis strikes down political smokescreens. Like this:
Politician: Here’s my program to make the health care system work better by subsidizing health care for the poor.
Economist: Your program costs a billion dollars and delivers half a billion dollars worth of benefits. That’s inefficient.
Politician: So what?
Economist: Well, the “so what” is that maybe you could take that billion dollars and deliver a full billion dollars worth of benefits instead if you spent it a little differently. Why not just hand the cash out to poor people?
Politician: Because I don’t want to help all poor people. I only want to help sick poor people — and this is the only way I can think of to do that.
Economist: Ah. So your goal here is not to make the health care system work better after all. Instead it’s to transfer resources to sick poor people.
Politician: I guess so.
Economist: That’s fine. Now we can have a healthy debate about whether that’s what we want to do.
“And now, you see, thanks to the economist’s insistence on thinking about efficiency, we end up having an honest debate about the politician’s real goal instead of a dishonest debate about the politician’s feigned goal. However the debate turns out, that’s a useful exercise.”
Landsburg, Steven, August 30, 2011, “Efficiency Experts”
Efficiency should not necessarily be the goal of society
But efficiency should be the goal of the legal system
If redistribution is desirable for justice, better to have the legal system be efficient, and redress distribution via taxes and spending
Taxes can target “rich” and “poor” more precisely than the legal system can
Distributional effects of legal changes are hard to predict
Transaction costs are higher for using the legal system (“Lawyers are more expensive than accountants”)
Broad-based taxes cause less distortion than narrowly-targeted laws/policies (or equivalent taxes)
Predicting consequences of law
Predicting what law will be
Recommending what law should be
Keyboard shortcuts
↑, ←, Pg Up, k | Go to previous slide |
↓, →, Pg Dn, Space, j | Go to next slide |
Home | Go to first slide |
End | Go to last slide |
Number + Return | Go to specific slide |
b / m / f | Toggle blackout / mirrored / fullscreen mode |
c | Clone slideshow |
p | Toggle presenter mode |
t | Restart the presentation timer |
?, h | Toggle this help |
Esc | Back to slideshow |